Graphics Reference
In-Depth Information
we may also assume that c = 0. Define an ordering < of N n-1 by:
(
) < (
)
ff
,
,...,
f
gg
,
,...,
g
if and only if
il
i
2
in
-
1
il
i
2
in
-
1
(
) < (
)
ff
,
,...,
f
,
0
gg
,
,...,
g
,
0
.
(10.63)
il
i
2
in
-
1
il
i
2
in
-
1
It is easy to check that this defines a monomial ordering on N n-1 . Our inductive
hypothesis applied to the sequence e i ¢=(e i1 ,e i2 ,...,e in-1 ) in now proves Claim 1.
If x = (x 1 ,x 2 ,..., x n ), y = (y 1 ,y 2 ,..., y n ) ΠN n-1
Claim 2.
satisfies x j < y j for all j,
then x < y .
Let d j = y j - x j and d = (d 1 ,d 2 ,...,d n ). Then 0 < d implies that x = 0 + x < d + x =
y and Claim 2 is proved.
Now consider the sequence in (10.62) again and assume that it is an infinite
sequence. If any of the sequences of nonnegative integers e ij , j = 1,2,..., is bounded
for some fixed i, then we can choose a subsequence of the e i so that the jth entries in
that subsequence are constant. By Claim 1 we would be done. Assume therefore that
the sequences e ij , j = 1,2,..., are unbounded for all i. Choose a subsequence of the e i
so that for that subsequence the first components form a strictly increasing sequence
of integers going to infinity. Let f i be this new decreasing sequence of elements of N n .
Now look at the second components of all the f i and choose a subsequence so that
the second components form a strictly increasing sequence of integers going to infin-
ity. Continue in this way until we finally end up with a subsequence g i = (g i1 ,g i2 ,
...,g in ) of the original sequence e i with the property that g i+1,j > g ij for all i and j. By
Claim 2 we would have g i+1 > g i , which is impossible since the sequence e i was decreas-
ing. This contradiction proves the theorem.
Theorem 10.10.3 is important because we need monomial orderings to have the
well-ordering property in addition to the total order to ensure that various algorithms
we shall define will terminate.
10.10.4. Proposition.
The lex, deglex, and degrevlex orders of k[X 1 ,X 2 ,...,X n ] are
monomial orderings.
Proof.
Obvious.
We need some more terminology before we can state the multivariable long divi-
sion theorem.
Definition. Fix a monomial order < on k[X 1 ,X 2 ,...,X n ] and let f Πk[X 1 ,X 2 ,...,X n ].
The largest monomial in f with respect to this order is called the leading term of f and
is denoted by lt(f). Its coefficient is called the leading coefficient and is denoted by lc(f).
The leading power product , denoted by lpp(f), is defined by the equation lt(f) =
lc(f)lpp(f) and is the largest power product appearing in f.
For example, assuming deglex order and Y < X, if
(
) =
2
fXY
,
7
XY XY Y
+
-
,
Search WWH ::




Custom Search