Biology Reference
In-Depth Information
and indeed much more likely to occur, when the research participants are vulner-
able . To correct the injustice, and thereby to prevent exploitation and protect the
vulnerable, benefit sharing is required. Benefits must be shared with the research
participants, if they would otherwise have no access to the products resulting from
the research, or, in our case, if they lack access to health care. There is a worry,
although we have argued that it is a misplaced worry, that such benefits may con-
stitute undue inducements to participate in such research. This is how the concepts
of vulnerability, exploitation, benefit sharing and undue inducements are related in
the context of research involving human participants in developing countries.
The concepts of vulnerability and exploitation are both vague and morally
charged. We should be careful about their use. We have suggested a relatively
precise definition of 'vulnerability' in the hope of both clarifying the concept and
avoiding its over-extension, which we have observed in recent years. According to
our definition, to be vulnerable means to face a significant probability of incurring
an identifiable harm, while substantially lacking the ability or means to protect one-
self. When we talk about vulnerable research participants we need to be clear about
what (sort of) harm they are vulnerable to. We have pointed out that one particularly
important marker for harm in research is the research participants' lack of access to
the benefits of research. This type of harm relates directly to exploitation. Following
Robert Mayer's account of exploitation, we have defined 'wrongful exploitation' as
a failure to benefit others as some norm of fairness requires. Wrongful exploitation
is particularly wrongful when it involves a failure to benefit vulnerable people.
From these considerations, we have developed a normative concept of benefit shar-
ing: those who contribute to developments in science and technology ought to share in
the benefits. The worry that such benefits may constitute undue inducements to partici-
pate in the research cannot be ignored, but in research that involves minimal risk, this
concern is largely misplaced and should not be used to avoid benefit sharing. The next
chapter discusses some of the benefit-sharing options available.
References
Annas G, Grodin M (1998) Human rights and maternal-fetal HIV transmission prevention trials
in Africa. Am J Public Health 88(4):560-563
Arnason G, Van Niekerk A (2009) Undue fear of inducements in research in developing coun-
tries. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 18(2):122-129
Ashcroft R (2008) Fair process and the redundancy of bioethics: a polemic. Public Health Ethics
1(1):3-9
Barclay L (2008) Exploitation and double standards in research in developed countries. Monash
Bioeth Rev 27(4):37-44
Bentley JP, Thacker PG (2004) The influence of risk and monetary payment on the research par-
ticipation decision making process. J Med Ethics 30:293-298
Berg K, Chadwick R (2001) Solidarity and equity: new ethical frameworks for genetic databases.
Nature Rev 2:318-321
Bonn Guidelines (2002) The Bonn Guidelines on Access to Genetic Resources and the Fair and
Equitable Sharing of the Benefits Arising out of their Utilization. Secretariat of the Convention
on Biological Diversity, Quebec. http://www.cbd.int/doc/publications/cbd-bonn-gdls-en.pdf
Search WWH ::




Custom Search